Thursday, 25 June 2015

The Ontological Argument - Refuted

These are the standard objections to argument #13 on the list provided here...

This is the argument...

1 It is greater for a thing to exist in the mind and in reality than in the mind alone.

2 "God" means "that than which a greater cannot be thought."

3 Suppose that God exists in the mind but not in reality.

4 Then a greater than God could be thought (namely, a being that has all the qualities our thought of God has plus real existence).

5 But this is impossible, for God is "that than which a greater cannot be thought."

6 Therefore God exists in the mind and in reality.


Standard Objections

The basis of the argument is the concept of God as the greatest being in order to imply that God exists. Otherwise there could be something greater, but this being would also be God.

An obvious way to highlight the fundamental flaw of the argument is to substitute something else for the word "God". For example , 

- The Perfect Pizza means "a pizza than which a greater pizza cannot be thought."

- Suppose that the Perfect Pizza exists in the mind but not in reality.

- Then a pizza greater than the Perfect Pizza could be thought (namely, a pizza that has all the qualities our thought of the Perfect Pizza has - plus real existence).

- But this is impossible for the Perfect Pizza is "a pizza than which a greater pizza cannot be thought."

- Therefore The Perfect Pizza exists in the mind and in reality.

Obviously - no one would reasonably conclude that the existence of the perfect pizza has thus been proven. Would they?

Note: The logical principle here is that true premises and a false conclusion can never occur in a valid argument. So if we can construct a similar argument to a given argument with the same form, with true premises and a false conclusion, then the given argument is invalid.

The definition of God as "that than which a greater cannot be thought" is impossible to understand and is circular - it defines the thing it is trying to prove. If person A asserts they can think of something greater than God, person B can either say "no you can't" or they could say "the greater thing you are now thinking of is God". So God is whatever you think God is. 

The argument compares the concept of existing in the mind with the concept of existing in reality. But an argument can only deal with concepts, not existent things in the external world. It is not logical to compare the value of the idea of 100 dollar bills with 100 real dollar bills. (On a wider point - it is wrong for anyone to suggest the 20 arguments are 'evidence". The arguments are based on logic, nor evidence. Inductive arguments are not evidence).

The concept of existence is itself problematic. Although we assume existence in our daily conversation and arguments, we do not prove existence. For example - You wouldn't describe your newly born baby to your friends and then say "Oh by the way, my baby really exists." Existence cannot be proven. As Kierkegaard points out, you cannot prove the existence of Napoleon by his deeds, because to mention his deeds is to assume the existence of someone who did them. So any such argument presupposes the existence of the subject it talks about.


Another flaw in the argument is the equivocation of different meanings of the word “God." - (1) A god who exists in reality and (2) a god who exists only in the mind. This leads to the collapse of premise 4 - Then a greater than God could be thought (namely a being... etc.) If this Greater God is a "thought" then it is a thing that exists in the mind. It doesn't exist in reality just because we have a thought that it exists in reality.

Monday, 22 June 2015

The Argument from Desire - Refuted

These are the standard objections to argument #16 on the list provided here...

The argument is formed as follows:

1 Every natural, innate desire in us corresponds to some real object that can satisfy that desire.

2 But there exists in us a desire which nothing in time, nothing on earth, no creature can satisfy.

3 Therefore there must exist something more than time, earth and creatures, which can satisfy this desire.

4 This something is what people call "God" and "life with God forever."

Standard Objections

This argument, famously proposed by CS Lewis, was never supposed to prove God's existence, but is often used erroneously for that purpose. 

Premise 2 refers to a desire which nothing can satisfy. Perhaps CS Lewis felt such a desire, perhaps many people do, and their belief in God satisfies that desire. But not everyone does, so this desire does not demonstrate the existence of God. A desire to have an explanation for everything, a desire to live forever, a desire for an eternal life with no suffering, all of these desires can be met by imagining gods. They do not provide evidence that those gods are real. The thought an idea of God is real - but God is not necessarily real.

Bearing in mind that the authors are using this argument to demonstrate the existence of the Christian God, then the argument fails by assuming that is the only God who can satisfy the desire it refers to. There have been, and still are, many gods who can fulfil the desire to believe in gods. 

The argument confuses needs and desires. natural innate desires for food and water and shelter are fundamental needs for life. If we need to eat, it is because we need to replace lost energy. Our physiology provides the signals to the brain which we experience as hunger. The desire to eat is something completely different and is more accurately described as a craving. It can lead to obesity. Such desires can be psychological in nature, or a result of peer pressure, culture, advertising etc. So is God a human need? Obviously not, because people are able to live happy and fulfilled lives without God. God is therefore a desire or a craving.


The argument is based on the assumption that a desire for something can prove that it exists. This is a false assumption. We can’t prove the existence of Santa Clause because we desire gifts on Christmas day. We can't prove food exists because we desire food. A desire for paradise and eternal life with God doesn’t prove that they exist.

Sunday, 7 June 2015

The Kalam Argument - Refuted


These are the standard objections to argument #6 on the list provided here...
 
This is a variation of the Cosmological argument but originating from Islamic theologians. This is the version presented in the above link...
 
- Whatever begins to exist has a cause for its coming into being.
- The universe began to exist.
- Therefore, the universe has a cause for its coming into being.
- The cause is God
This argument is subject to many well know objections most of which demonstrate the the argument falls over at the first premise due to the assumption that the appearance of our universe is an event just like any other event, when this might not be the case.
Religious apologists state the premise as an axiomatic truth. The premise certainly appeals intuitively to our human experience, but we don't know if our intuitive experience applies to everything so it is not necessarily true to say that "whatever begins to exist has a cause." For example, it is possible that the universe is part of a multiverse which had no cause. Or any other number of explanations. We simply don't know.
(This is a basic flaw with all "uncaused cause" arguments which arbitrarily;y assign God as the uncaused cause. The uncaused cause - if there is a cause - could be anything. In addition, and as stated in argument #2, there is quantum evidence for different mechanisms for events, and this includes events with no cause, simultaneous causation, backward causation and so on. The other old argument here is the infinite regression which apologists arbitrarily claim stops with God simply to avoid the "who created God" argument.)
The second premise also seems obvious given the evidence of the Big Bang, but the appearance of our universe cannot necessarily be included in the "whatever" assumption of the first premise even if the first premise was true - which it might not be. As already explained, the "whatever" is based on our everyday observations of events within the universe. But the appearance of our universe is not an everyday event and is obviously not an event comparable to the events within itself and resulting from its existence.  There is even an argument that the Big Bang is not a physical event at all because an event, by definition, occurs at a specific time and there was no time at the Big Bang At least one mathematical model shows that as we rewind time the universe approaches the state of singularity but never actually reaches it and so has no beginning and hence no cause.  Plus it's not just time that was absent at the Big Bang. Every physical law or mechanism that we identify with our everyday experience of events is absent at the Big Bang. 
 
All of the above means the conclusion on line three does not necessarily follow. And of course the final statement that the "cause is God" is simply an assertion. It would be just as logical to say the cause is a vacuum fluctuation, or the Great Green Arkleseizure. Or gods. Or Odin, or any number of things.
 
One of the most well known and comprehensive refutations of the Kalam Argument is provided in chapter 8 of the book "Godless." Within the chapter on pages 131/132 is a simple mathematical refutation:
The clause “whatever begins to exist” implies that reality can be divided into two sets: things that begin to exist (BE), and things that do not (NBE). 
In order for this argument to work, NBE (if such a set is meaningful) cannot be empty. If NBE was empty it would mean that there is nothing that does not begin to exist, which means everything has a beginning, which means God would have a beginning. 
 
So NBE cannot be empty, but also, it must contain more than one item. If we assume it only contains one item then we are creating a premise that says there is only one thing that does not begin to exist, which is what the argument is trying to prove. So that assumption would result in the fallacious argument of begging the question.

In other words, NBE must contain more than one item. which means that if the universe has a cause, there are several possibilities for the cause of the universe.